What is Ethical Subjectivism? Personal Morality

12 minutes on read

Ethical subjectivism, a philosophical concept, posits that moral judgments reflect individual preferences, emotions, or attitudes, thereby aligning personal morality with subjective viewpoints. Unlike moral realism, which asserts objective moral truths, ethical subjectivism denies the existence of universal moral standards, suggesting that moral statements are neither true nor false in an objective sense. David Hume, a prominent philosopher, influenced this perspective through his emphasis on the role of sentiment and emotion in moral evaluations. Cultural relativism, the belief that moral standards vary across cultures, often intersects with ethical subjectivism by highlighting the diversity of moral beliefs and practices. The implications of what is ethical subjectivism extend to debates about moral relativism and moral nihilism, offering various perspectives on the nature of morality and its grounding in individual experience.

Understanding Ethical Subjectivism: A Meta-Ethical Exploration

Ethical subjectivism stands as a significant, and often debated, meta-ethical theory.

It posits that moral judgments are fundamentally rooted in individual perspectives, feelings, or beliefs, rather than corresponding to objective, universal facts.

This perspective implies that when we declare something "good" or "bad," we are, in essence, expressing our personal sentiments or opinions about it.

Defining Ethical Subjectivism

At its core, ethical subjectivism is a meta-ethical position.

It deals not with the content of morality itself (what actions are right or wrong), but rather with the nature of moral judgments.

The central claim is that moral statements reflect individual attitudes, emotions, or beliefs.

These assertions lack objective truth value in the traditional sense.

Instead of describing an external reality, they function as expressions of personal subjectivity.

The Subjective Nature of Moral Statements

A key tenet of ethical subjectivism is the assertion that moral statements are not objective truths.

Consider the statement "Honesty is good."

From a subjectivist perspective, this statement does not reflect an inherent property of honesty itself.

Instead, it communicates the speaker's approval of honesty.

It effectively translates to "I approve of honesty" or "Honesty aligns with my personal values."

Key Concepts in Ethical Subjectivism

Understanding ethical subjectivism requires familiarity with several key concepts that illuminate its scope and implications.

Meta-Ethics

Meta-ethics is the branch of ethics that investigates the meaning of moral language and the foundations of moral beliefs. Ethical subjectivism falls squarely within this domain, as it seeks to explain what moral judgments are, rather than what they should be.

Personal Values and Subjective Experience

Ethical subjectivism places immense emphasis on the role of personal values and subjective experience in shaping moral beliefs.

Individual backgrounds, cultural influences, and personal experiences all contribute to the formation of unique moral perspectives.

Truth Value, Moral Disagreement, and Relativism

The concept of truth value is central to the debate surrounding ethical subjectivism. If moral judgments are merely expressions of personal feeling, they lack objective truth value. This raises complex questions about the nature of moral disagreement and whether genuine moral agreement is even possible. Moral relativism, the idea that morality is relative to individuals or cultures, often emerges as a consequence of subjectivist viewpoints.

Moral Objectivism vs. Moral Skepticism

Ethical subjectivism stands in direct contrast to moral objectivism, which asserts the existence of objective moral truths independent of individual opinions.

It also intersects with moral skepticism, which questions the possibility of moral knowledge altogether.

The Individual Mind

Ultimately, ethical subjectivism locates moral authority within the individual mind.

Each person is seen as the ultimate arbiter of their own moral standards. This emphasis on individual autonomy has profound implications for how we understand ethics, law, and social interaction.

A Historical Journey: The Roots of Subjectivism

Understanding Ethical Subjectivism: A Meta-Ethical Exploration Ethical subjectivism stands as a significant, and often debated, meta-ethical theory. It posits that moral judgments are fundamentally rooted in individual perspectives, feelings, or beliefs, rather than corresponding to objective, universal facts. This perspective implies that when we... trace its historical roots, we are engaging with a lineage of thought that has profoundly shaped our understanding of morality itself.

The Genesis of Subjectivism: Protagoras and the Measure of All Things

The genesis of subjectivism can be traced back to ancient Greece, with Protagoras often cited as a pivotal figure. His famous dictum, "Man is the measure of all things," encapsulates a fundamental principle of subjectivism.

This assertion suggests that reality, including moral reality, is relative to individual perception. What is considered "good" or "right" is not an inherent property but is determined by the individual experiencing it.

Protagoras's notion challenges the idea of objective moral standards, laying the groundwork for later subjectivist theories. His focus on human experience as the basis for knowledge and value is a crucial starting point in understanding the development of ethical subjectivism.

Hume's Sentimentalism: The Role of Emotion in Moral Evaluation

Moving forward to the Enlightenment, David Hume significantly contributed to the development of subjectivism through his emphasis on emotion and sentiment in moral evaluations. Hume argued that reason alone cannot motivate moral action.

Instead, he posited that our moral judgments are primarily driven by feelings of approval or disapproval. These sentiments, according to Hume, are the foundation upon which we construct our moral systems.

Hume’s sentimentalism suggests that morality is not about discovering objective truths but about expressing subjective emotional responses.

This focus on emotion as a central component of moral judgment is a key element in understanding the evolution of subjectivist thought. Hume’s work marks a departure from rationalist approaches to ethics, emphasizing the role of human experience in shaping moral values.

Nietzsche's Perspectivism: Morality as a Human Construct

In the 19th century, Friedrich Nietzsche offered a radical perspective on morality, further solidifying the subjectivist tradition. Nietzsche's perspectivism posits that there is no objective truth. Knowledge and values are always interpreted from a particular viewpoint.

For Nietzsche, morality is a human construct, created to serve particular interests and power dynamics. He challenged the idea of universal moral principles, arguing that moral systems are often tools used to control and manipulate individuals.

Nietzsche's critique of traditional morality and his emphasis on the will to power profoundly impacted the development of subjectivist thought.

His work questions the very foundation of moral claims, suggesting that they are ultimately expressions of subjective preferences and power relations.

Emotivism: A.J. Ayer, C.L. Stevenson, and the Expression of Emotion

In the 20th century, Emotivism emerged as a prominent form of ethical subjectivism, articulated by philosophers such as A.J. Ayer and C.L. Stevenson. Emotivism holds that moral statements do not express facts or beliefs but rather express emotions or attitudes.

According to emotivists, when we say something is "good" or "bad," we are essentially expressing our feelings of approval or disapproval.

Moral statements, therefore, lack cognitive content and cannot be true or false. Emotivism focuses on the expressive function of moral language, viewing it as a way to influence the attitudes and actions of others.

Ayer and Stevenson emphasize that the primary purpose of ethical assertions is to vent emotions or exert influence, rather than to describe objective moral realities. This perspective reinforces the subjectivist notion that moral values are rooted in subjective human experience.

L. Mackie's Error Theory: The Denial of Objective Moral Values

J.L. Mackie offered another distinctive perspective on subjectivism through his Error Theory. Mackie contended that all moral claims are false.

He argued that objective moral values simply do not exist. When we make moral assertions, we are mistakenly projecting our subjective feelings onto the world.

According to Mackie, moral judgments are based on a false belief in objective moral properties. His error theory suggests that while people genuinely attempt to express objective moral facts, these attempts are inherently flawed because there are no objective moral facts to express.

Mackie's error theory takes subjectivism to its extreme, denying the validity of all moral claims. It presents a stark challenge to traditional moral beliefs, arguing that morality is based on a fundamental error in understanding the nature of value.

Core Principles: Dissecting Ethical Subjectivism

Building upon the historical foundations of ethical subjectivism, it is crucial to examine the core tenets that define this meta-ethical position.

Ethical subjectivism hinges on several key principles concerning the nature of moral judgments, the role of individual experience, and the locus of moral authority.

The Absence of Objective Truth Value

At the heart of ethical subjectivism lies the assertion that moral judgments do not possess objective truth value. Unlike statements of empirical fact, such as "the Earth revolves around the Sun," moral claims like "honesty is good" are not considered true or false in any mind-independent sense.

Rather, they are expressions of personal feelings, attitudes, or beliefs. This is inextricably linked to the role of subjective experience in shaping our moral outlook.

Our individual backgrounds, emotions, and perceptions contribute significantly to how we evaluate and respond to moral issues.

The same action may elicit feelings of approval in one person and disapproval in another, reflecting differing subjective experiences.

The Primacy of Personal Values

Personal values occupy a central position within ethical subjectivism. These values, which are shaped by a multitude of factors, including upbringing, culture, and personal experiences, serve as the foundation for individual moral codes.

For a subjectivist, moral decision-making is essentially an exercise in aligning actions with one's deeply held values.

What one individual deems morally praiseworthy may clash with another's moral compass, given the heterogeneity of personal values across individuals and societies.

The Emergence of Moral Relativism

Ethical subjectivism gives rise to a form of moral relativism. Since moral judgments are ultimately grounded in individual perspectives, morality becomes contingent on the viewpoint of the individual.

There is no universal moral standard to which everyone is bound.

Each person is, in effect, the ultimate arbiter of their own moral code.

This does not necessarily imply that anything goes, but rather that moral evaluation is always relative to a specific frame of reference – namely, the individual’s own values and beliefs.

The Individual Mind as Moral Authority

Perhaps the most significant implication of ethical subjectivism is the relocation of moral authority within the individual mind.

In contrast to moral objectivism, which posits the existence of objective moral truths independent of human opinion, subjectivism places the power of moral determination squarely in the hands of each person.

The individual becomes the ultimate judge of what is right and wrong for themselves.

This emphasis on individual autonomy can be seen as both empowering and problematic, as it simultaneously affirms the importance of personal moral agency while potentially undermining the possibility of shared moral standards.

Challenging Moral Objectivism

Ethical subjectivism presents a fundamental challenge to traditional notions of moral objectivism.

Objectivists argue that moral truths exist independently of human opinions or feelings, much like scientific facts. Subjectivism rejects this view, contending that morality is inherently subjective and variable.

This clash between subjectivism and objectivism represents a central point of contention in meta-ethical debates.

The question of whether morality is grounded in objective reality or subjective experience continues to fuel philosophical discussions.

The Specter of Moral Skepticism

Finally, it is important to consider the relationship between ethical subjectivism and moral skepticism. Skepticism about morality questions the possibility of moral knowledge.

If moral judgments are merely expressions of personal feelings, can we ever truly know what is right or wrong?

While not all subjectivists are moral skeptics, subjectivism can provide fertile ground for skeptical arguments.

The absence of objective moral standards may lead some to conclude that moral knowledge is unattainable, further complicating the landscape of ethical theory.

Implications and Critiques: Exploring the Consequences

Building upon the core principles of ethical subjectivism, it is vital to consider the real-world implications of adopting such a framework. This section delves into the consequences of ethical subjectivism, examining its capacity to address moral disagreements and the criticisms leveled against it, particularly concerning moral anarchy and conflict resolution. We will further analyze the impact of subjectivism on moral education and character development.

Moral Disagreement in a Subjectivist World

A central challenge for ethical subjectivism lies in explaining and addressing moral disagreements. If moral truths are merely expressions of individual feelings or opinions, how can meaningful dialogue or resolution of conflicting moral viewpoints occur?

Subjectivism suggests that moral debates are not about discovering objective truths but rather about negotiating personal preferences or attempting to persuade others to adopt a particular viewpoint.

This perspective raises questions about the nature of moral progress and the possibility of shared moral understanding. Can societies build common ethical ground if morality is fundamentally subjective?

Critiques of Ethical Subjectivism

Ethical subjectivism faces numerous criticisms, primarily centered on the potential for moral anarchy and the difficulty of resolving ethical conflicts.

Critics argue that if each individual's moral beliefs are equally valid, there is no basis for condemning harmful actions or promoting prosocial behavior.

The Problem of Moral Anarchy

The specter of moral anarchy looms large in discussions of subjectivism.

If morality is reduced to personal preference, there appears to be no logical reason to prevent individuals from acting on even the most destructive impulses, provided they genuinely believe such actions are morally acceptable.

This leads to the unsettling conclusion that heinous acts, such as violence, oppression, and discrimination, could be justified simply by an individual's subjective approval.

The Challenge of Conflict Resolution

Furthermore, subjectivism presents significant obstacles to resolving ethical conflicts.

When individuals hold opposing moral views, and there is no objective standard to adjudicate between them, reaching a mutually agreeable solution becomes exceedingly difficult.

Dialogue may devolve into mere expressions of personal feelings, devoid of rational argumentation or the pursuit of shared understanding.

In such a scenario, power dynamics and social pressures may determine the outcome, rather than reasoned ethical deliberation.

Implications for Moral Education and Character

The implications of ethical subjectivism for moral education are far-reaching and complex.

If morality is subjective, what should be taught in schools and families about right and wrong?

Traditional approaches to moral education often rely on the transmission of established norms and values, grounded in religious, philosophical, or cultural traditions.

However, subjectivism challenges the authority of these traditions, suggesting that individuals should be free to construct their own moral codes.

This raises questions about the role of educators in shaping moral character and the potential for promoting ethical relativism rather than robust moral reasoning.

Should moral education focus on cultivating critical thinking skills and encouraging students to explore diverse perspectives, or should it aim to instill specific values and principles?

The answers to these questions depend, in large part, on one's stance on the objectivity or subjectivity of moral truths.

FAQs: Ethical Subjectivism & Personal Morality

If ethical subjectivism is true, are all moral opinions equally valid?

Yes, according to what is ethical subjectivism, all moral opinions are equally valid. Since morality is based solely on individual feelings or beliefs, one person's moral judgment is no better or worse than another's.

Doesn't ethical subjectivism lead to moral chaos or anarchy?

Ethical subjectivism can seem to open the door to moral chaos. If "right" and "wrong" are purely personal, what prevents someone from doing terrible things and claiming it's morally acceptable to them? The theory's main weakness is that it cannot support the notion of objective moral truth.

How is ethical subjectivism different from simple preference?

While preferences like "I like chocolate" are subjective, ethical subjectivism applies this subjectivity to moral claims. It means statements like "Murder is wrong" are not objectively true, but simply express the speaker's disapproval or feeling towards murder, similar to expressing a food preference. Therefore, what is ethical subjectivism is using personal preferences as a definition for moral good.

Does ethical subjectivism allow for moral disagreement?

Surprisingly, ethical subjectivism suggests that what seems like moral disagreement is often something else. If morality is purely personal, then when two people disagree about whether something is right or wrong, they are not contradicting each other. Each person is merely reporting their own feelings or beliefs, much like stating different personal preferences.

So, where does that leave us? Basically, ethical subjectivism boils down to the idea that morality is all about personal opinion. What's "right" for you might not be "right" for me, and that's okay. It's definitely a perspective that encourages tolerance and individual freedom, but it also brings up some pretty interesting questions about how we navigate a world where everyone has their own version of the truth.